Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Nathanael Tekalign's avatar

Response #6: The argument in your article is probably made to pre-empt the argument from reasonable disagreement against reasonableness-oriented social contract theory. My argument goes as follows:

Premise #1: reasonableness-oriented social contract theory says that there is a social contract hypothetical or actual) which could not be reasonably rejected.

Premise #2: reasonableness-oriented social contract theory also says that such social contract, by virtue of being impossible to reasonably reject, is binding on those who unreasonably reject it.

Premise #3: If reasonableness-oriented social contract theory is true, then whatever reasonable disagreement exists about morality could be explained by disagreement about descriptive facts.

Premise #4: There exists reasonable disagreement about morality which can’t be explained by disagreement about descriptive facts.

Conclusion: Therefore, reasonableness-oriented social contract theory is false.

Expand full comment
Nathanael Tekalign's avatar

Response #1: If saving 5 lives doesn’t justify single-victim MURDER, but saving 5 lives justifies single-victim MANSLAUGHTER, then something OTHER than the most reasonable social contract (I.e. whichever social contract could not be reasonably rejected) renders such distinction relevant.

Response #2: In the Switch version of the trolley problem, the innocents are tied up to the tracks through no fault of their own.

Response #3: Your distinction of harmful side effects vs equally harmful means is probably derived from the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE).

Response #4: Ezio Di Nucci made 8 different arguments as to why intentions are irrelevant in contexts where the DDE treats intentions as relevant.

Response #5: The whole point of trolley problems is to show that morality gives an objectively true answer to a given issue even if someone, somewhere, reasonably rejects it.

Expand full comment

No posts